X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (2024)

Learning Objectives

By the end of this chapter, you should be able to,

  • identify intermediate levels (“bar levels”) using constituency tests
  • understand the motivation for the X-bar schema
  • draw a tree using the X-bar schema,
  • identify the distinct positions within the X-bar schema,
  • diagnose the difference between adjuncts and complements

By the end of this chapter, we will have technically changed theories. We’re going from Phrase Structure Grammars to X-bar Syntax. But the trick is to recognize that, even though we’re going to be using the term “X-bar syntax,” we aren’t actually changing theories at all. The same principles, formalizations, and theoretical tools will be used in X-bar syntax that we’ve already been using. Our trees are just going to look more complicated. The reason that our trees will look more complicated is that we’re going to discover in this chapter that there are lot of “hidden” layers. Just like when we discussed functional categories we learned to infer the presence of structure, even when we can’t directly see it, we’ll use the same tools to infer the presence of “bar-levels.”

From this, we’ll make a theoretical leap. As a hypothesis about syntax, we’ll adopt a uniform structural representation for all phrases. This is “X-bar syntax.” It’s the hypothesis that all phrases share a structure, i.e., every phrase looks identical. The hypothesis makes a number of testable predictions, which we’ll explore in terms of the complement/adjunct distinction.

Let’s start by looking again at English VPs. Assume the (very simplistic) rule for VPs below.

Simplified VP rule for English (to be revised)

  • VP → V (DP) (PP)+

This rule allows us to minimally distinguish between transitive and intransitive verbs, each of which could have a modifying prepositional phrase. For instance, using this VP rule, here’s the structure for The doctor will sing a song in the park.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (1)

This tree correctly represents that in the park is a constituent. It also correctly represents thatsing a song in the park is a constituent. However, it still is getting the constituency wrong. Look at the substitution test below. What does it show is a constituent?

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (2)

What’s the problem here? The test demonstrates thatsing a song is a constituent, because I am able to replace that string with do so. The tree in (1) gets this wrong. The string sing a song isn’t a constituent according to this tree because there is no node that contains the words sing a song and nothing else.

Is our constituency test just giving us a false positive? Let’s confirm. Below I’m applying the other constituency tests.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (3)

So our constituency tests are telling us thatsing a song is a constituent—and that it’s a VP. Recall that substitution and coordination allow us to diagnose the category of the constituent. But here’s the thing: the string sing a song in the park isalso a VP. How do I know? It passes all the same constituency tests, and we can detect its category through substitution and coordination.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (4)

So based on this evidence, it looks like our tree should actually have the following representation.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (5)

This version of the tree correctly captures our empirical result: we have two distinct VP constituents. (It also correctly predicts that a song in the park is not a constituent, which you can confirm on your own.) The “trick” is that we’ve added a VPin-between the head and the highest VP. This projection is empirically motivated, though. It’s there because our tests tell us it’s there. (Note that technically, the highest VP violates the Headedness Principle.)

We call this intermediate projection the “bar” level, and write it either with a line over the top (V) or an apostrophe after (V’). It’s pronounced “V bar” (not “V prime”). This is just a notation for saying “I’m not the highest phrase in this phrase.”

To review: we’ve used our constituency tests to determine that there is a “hidden” level in verb phrases.

Let’s look at more data.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (6)

These data are just like the data above, except that I’ve added in more prepositional phrases. So now sing a song on a bike can’t be the highest VP in the structure. The highest VP is the entire constituent sing a song on a bike in the park. This is the topmost VP. Now in fact, we need two intermediate projections, because the constituentssing a song andsing a song on a bike andsing a song on a bike in the park are all VPs.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (7)

These data actually suggest that I can simplify my representation quite a bit, because they suggest that I can make do without the “+” symbol. All I need are three rules like the following. Note that three rules is actually simpler than one rule with a plus sign because now we can get by with less formalism. By analogy, 2 + 2 + 2 is simpler than 2 x 3 because it provides the same information with a less complex operator.

Simplified VP rule for English (revised)

  • VP → V’
  • V’ → V’ PP
  • V’ → V (DP)

I’ve done a very tricky (but ultimately useful) thing here. I’ve explicitly addedrecursion into my English phrase structure grammar. There’s a rule that says V’ (i.e., an intermediate projection between the head and the topmost VP) can consist of itself and a prepositional phrase. Why does this work? Consider the tree for John will sing a song on a bikein the park which uses the new rule above.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (8)

When I build a VP now, I have an option: I can either add in an infinite number of prepositional phrases by adding in a new V’ level, or I can just go directly to the head V. I’ve essentially created a way to make an infinitely recursive loop—with an escape hatch. Most importantly, all of these intermediate projections correlate with distinct, identifiable constituents. That is, our structure correctly represents how English packages its information.

We can do the exact same thing with TP. Let’s assume our rule for TP developed in the last chapter.

TP rule for English (to be revised)

  • TP → DP T VP

Now consider the following data, which suggests that there is a bar-level—an intermediate projection—in TP.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (9)

What is this data showing? It shows that I can coordinatewill eat sushi with something else. That is, there appears to be a constituent that include T and VP, but does not include the subject. This is not possible, according to our rule above. To fix this issue, we can re-write our rule, parallel to what we did with VP.

TP rule for English (revised)

  • TP → DP T’
  • T’ → T VP

Adding in this extra level correctly captures what our constituency test is telling us.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (10)

This tree now correctly captures the fact that T forms a constituent with VP, to the exclusion of the subject. That constituent is the bar level, T’.

What if I add in more words. Here I’m adding a modifier of TP.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (11)

This data now suggests that the modifier gets grouped together with T and the VP in the first example (because both constituents have a similar modifier), but in the second example shows us that T and the VP can form a constituent that isseparate from this modifier (because definitely is describing both the eating and drinking events). How are we going to make this work? If Adverbs[1] likedefinitely, probably, etc may sometimes be distinct from the VP, and sometimes not, we need to adjust our rules about where adverbs go in TP.

Just like with VP, we can fix this issue concisely by adding a recursive T’ level!

TP rule for English (revised)

  • TP → DP T’
  • T’ → AdvP T’
  • T’ → T VP

This set of rules allows us to add as many modifiers of TP as we want, and we will always find that each additional modifier “creates” a subconstituent within TP.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (12)

We’ll do the exact same thing with NP. Keep in mind that we’ve adopted the DP-hypothesis, so all NPs are inside of DPs.

Simplified NP rule for English (to be revised)

  • NP → (AP)+ N

With this rule in mind, consider the patterns ofone substitution shown below.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (13)

We observed in the last chapter thatone substituted for NP, but these data suggest that that isn’t quite accurate. One must be substituting for something between NP and N. Consider (16b).One is replacing the constituent blue book. This includes an adjective, so it’s not just the head N, but it excludes the higher adjectiveshort/long, so this cannot be the entire NP.

We therefore find evidence in NP for an intermediate projection, and we re-write our rules accordingly. Now we can add in an infinite number of prenominal adjectives by adding in more intermediate projections.

Simplified NP rule for English (revised)

  • NP → N’
  • N’ → AdjP N’
  • N’ → N

These rules correspond to the following tree.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (14)

When we look across all of our rules, we can make a few generalizations:

  • There’s always a rule of the form XP → X’, where the phrase level goes to the intermediate level. (Sometimes this rule has an element in front of X’.)
  • There’s always a rule of the form X’ → X, where the bar-level consists of the head. (Sometimes the head is followed by something on the right.)
  • There’s always a recursive rule of the form X’ →YP X’ or X’ → X’ YP, where YP is a modifier of some sort.

If this pattern exists for every single category, it suggests that we can generalize our schema for phrase structure. We hypothesize that every phrase has the following rules. The “X, Y, Z, W” below are variables meaning “any category.”

Generalized phrase structures rules (final version)

  • XP → (YP) X’
  • X’ → X’ ZP
  • X’ → ZP X’
  • X’ → X (WP)

If this is right, it means that all phrases are constructed based on these rules. In the rules above X, Y, and W are variables over categories.

What about the Headedness Principle? Have we entirely abandoned it? No! The Headedness Principle, which says that every phrase has a head and every head is in its phrase is exactly the same.But we’ve redefined what “phrase” means.Now a phrase minimally involves at least one X’-level. A phrase consists ofall of the rules above: it is the X-bar schema. The term “phrase” is now a structural notion.

The X-bar schema is a hypothesis. By looking at a lot of data, we identify that there are intermediate projections in every phrase that we look at. The subsequent phrase structure rules all end up looking very similar—suspiciously similar in fact. The X-bar schema is a way to make sense of this information. It proposes that the similarities reflect a “deep” uniformity across syntax. Our trees end up looking more complex, because now everything needs at least one intermediate projection. But the complexity of the representations comes with an overall simplification of the theory: it isn’t necessary to learn a bunch of arbitrary rules for syntax. You only need the four above, because they apply to every phrasal category.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (15)

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (16)

Trees in the X’ schema (length: 1m 28s)

Note we also still need special rules for coordination, which look basically the same as before.

Rules for coordination (final version)

  • XP → XP conj XP
  • X’ → X’ conj X’
  • X → X conj X

These rules allow you to coordinate heads (X), bar-levels (X’) and phrases (XP), but you can’t mix-and-match. You cannot coordinate a bar level with a head, for instance.

We define four positions within the X’-schema: specifier, head, complement and adjunct. The positions are indicated in the trees below.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (17)

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (18)

  • A head is the only non-phrasal terminal node in a phrase.
  • A specifier is defined as, “The phrase that is daughter of XP and sister to X.” Every phrase that meets this description is a specifier.
  • A complement is defined as, “The phrase that is sister to X and daughter to X.” Every phrase that meets this description is a complement.[2]
  • An adjunct is defined as, “The phrase that is daughter to X and sister to X.” Every phrase that meets this description is an adjunct.

Note that the definitions above do not make reference tolinear order. It doesn’t matter whether an adjunct is to the left or the right. All that matters is that its sister and mother are bar-levels. Likewise, complements can be on the left or the right of a head, as long as it is sister to the head. And a specifier can be on the left right as well, as long its mother is a phrase. Every language makes particular choices however about where specifiers and complements appear. We’ll return to this momentarily. For now, we note that in English, specifiers arealways on the left, and complements arealways on the right.

It is conventional to use the “genealogical” termsmother, sister,anddaughter when referring to the relationships between elements in a tree. The terms are meant to be transparent: A “mother” is something that has “daughters.” If two things have the same mother, then they’re “sisters.”

In the tree below, DP is the mother of D’. D’ is the mother of D and NP. D and NP are sisters, and are both daughters of D’.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (19)

The analogy basically stops there. There is no such thing as an “aunt” in syntax, or a “niece.”

We’ve seen a lot of complements. TP is a complement to CP. NP is a complement to D. DP can be a complement to V when it’s an object of the verb. The only specifier we’ve seen is the subject. It’s the specifier of TP. There is another place where a specifier is necessary: DP.

Possessive structure.

The other place where we observe specifiers is in possessive DPs.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (20)

We treat the possessive marker -s as a realization of D. This is because possessives are in complementary distribution with determiners: *the mailman’s the bag. And because the entire DP acts as a constituent referring to a bag, not a mailman, the head of the highest DP must be the possessive D.

Possessive DPs (length: 1m 51s)

The X-bar schema illustrated above makes a prediction that some phrases that are next to a head are complements while some are adjuncts. They may look identical on the surface, but they derive from different structures.

For instance, consider the phrase the state of Kansas. In the X-bar schema, this constituent (and it definitely is a constituent) could hypothetically correspond to either tree below. The prepositional phraseof Kansas could either be a complement tostate (as in the tree on the left) or an adjunct tostate (as in the tree on the right).

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (21)

The two trees actually make distinct empirical predictions. We have three tests to distinguish between complements and adjuncts.

First, I just want to briefly mention that it is easy to confuse adjuncts and specifiers. When drawing your trees, remember that for every adjunct, you should have “plus one” bar-level, because adjuncts need both a bar-level which is a sister, and bar-level which is a mother. So you have to add a layer whenever you add an adjunct.

Adjuncts in X’-syntax (length: 2m 15s)

Substitution

The constituency test of substitution has a different use. As we observed above, one substitution and do so substitution both target the bar-level. Since complements are under all bar-levels in a phrase, if you try to do substitution, a complement cannot be “left behind.” An adjunct can, though, because there’s always a bar-level that doesn’t include the adjunct.

Visually, consider the two trees again. If the PP is a complement to N, then when you substitute withone everything under N’ has to go too. In contrast, if the PP is an adjunct, it’s possible to substitute with one and leave behind the PP.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (22)

So to use the substitution test to determine if something is a complement or adjunct, you simply replace thehead of the phrase, and see if you can leave behind the constituent in question.

Compare the sentences below.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (23)

As illustrated above, one-substitution crucially yields an ungrammatical result in (19a), but not in (19b). Why is this? Again, note here that one-substitution targets bar-levels; you can only replace the material that exists under a bar-level. As such, the reason for the grammaticality distinction in the examples above is that the NPs, the state of Kansas and the state near Kansas, crucially differ in the number of bar-levels they contain. That is, unlike in the NP, [ NP state of Kansas ], where one-substitution can replace both N and PP (20a), but not N alone (20b), with the NP, [NP state near Kansas ], one-substitution can either replace the larger constituent containing N and PP (21a), or N alone (21b), meaning that the NP in (19) must crucially contain two bar-levels, and the NP in (20), only one.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (24)

Since we have defined a complement as being the sister of the head that selects it, and the daughter of the bar-level that contains that same head (i.e. a head and its complement share a bar-level parent), while conversely defining an adjunct as being both the sister to a bar-level and the daughter to a bar-level, the fact that one-substitution can target two different constituents in (21) means that the NP, the state near Kansas, necessarily contains two bar-levels, and, therefore, must contain an adjunct. That is, the PP, near Kansas, must be an adjunct because there are two different targets (i.e. bar-levels) for one-substitution in (20); one can replace the lower bar-level to the exclusion of PP, i.e. [ N’ [ N state ]], orit can replace the higher bar-level that includes both the lower N’ and PP, i.e. [ N’ [N’ [ N state][ PP near Kansas ]].

Step-by-step walkthrough of the substitution test

  • Identify the head in question and the phrase which you want to test
  • Identify the appropriate substitution word for the head.
  • Replace the head with the substitution word, but don’t replace the phrase you’re testing. (Note that technically, you’re substituting at the lowest bar-level, which contains the head. The lowest bar-level could, in principle also have a complement.)
  • Check the grammaticality.

Substitution test for complements vs. adjuncts (length: 1m 6s)

Substitution test for complements vs. adjuncts (length: 1m 9s) Credit Damian White Lightning

Reordering

Complements must appear as sisters to the head, and so they have a fixed position with respect to other phrases. But adjuncts can, theoretically, be reordered. This is because all that’s necessary is that they have a mother that’s a bar-level and a sister that’s a bar-level.

For instance, consider the following trees which each have two prepositional phrases. The tree on the left treats PP1 as an complement and PP2 as an adjunct. If we switched their positions, then we switch their roles.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (25)

In contrast, in the tree on the right, both the PPs are adjuncts. It shouldn’t matter whether we switch their positions, because they both will still be adjuncts.

What this means is that if a constituent is a complement, it cannot be reordered with another constituent. If a constituent is an adjunct, it can be.

The difference can be shown empirically in the following examples. You can’t reorderof Kansas andnear Maine, suggesting thatof Kansas is a complement tostate. In contrast, you can reorderby the ocean andnear Maine, so we conclude thatby the ocean is an adjunct tostate.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (26)

Step-by-step walkthrough of the reordering test

  • Identify the head and the phrase which you want to test.
  • Choose an appropriate phrase that can appear with the head and phrase above.
  • Reorder or the two phrases with respect to the head, and check the grammaticality.

Reordering test (length: 1m 2s)

Reordering test (length: 1m 6s) Credit: Damian White Lightning

Sometimes we can’t reorder phrases for semantic reasons, independent (presumably) of syntax. There happens to be a fixed order for modification that is fairly robust cross-linguistically. For instance, temporal modifiers (things that deal with “time”) tend to be merged higher (or “outside”) of manner modifiers (things that describe “how” the event was accomplished). Likewise, there is a fairly fixed ordering of adjectives in English (and many languages).

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (27)

Linear ordering

As a corollary to the last test, if you can’t reorder the phrases, the phrase nearest the head must be a complement. In fact, we predict that complements are always strictly adjacent to the head. Therefore, it should be impossible to insert anything between a head and complement. (Note that this test is irrelevant (N/A) if you find that you can reorder the phrase in question.)

Again, the difference is shown empirically below.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (28)

Step-by-step walkthrough of linear ordering test

  • Identify the head and the phrase you want to know about.
  • Identify some other constituent that can also directly follow the head.
  • Put the phrase you want to know about after the new phrase, both after the head, and check the grammaticality.

Linear ordering test (length: 1m 10s)

The reason that this test works is that the relationship between the head and complement is fixed: they must be sisters. But the relationship between a head and an adjunct is not fixed; there can be any number of adjuncts be between the head and the adjunct.

Based on the three tests above, we find that of Kansas is a complement tostate. So the following is the correct representation:

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (29)

The order of the specifiers and complements is fixed for any one language. What does that mean? For instance, in English, the complement always comesafter the head. That is, English ishead-initial. With specifiers, the specifier always comes before the head. English isspecifier-initial.

However, logically for each position, there are four ways things could be.

  • Specifier-initial : The specifier is to the left of its head (meaning to the left of the bar-level).
  • Specifier-final : The specifier is to the right of its head (meaning to the right of the bar-level).
  • Head-initial : The head is the left of its complement.
  • Head-final : The head is to the right of its complement.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (30)

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (31)

It turns out that languages make different choices as to how they order their heads and specifiers (and adjuncts). This is called parametric variation. English is specifier-initial and head-initial. Thus, in “neutral” contexts, it will have the order of Subject-Verb-Object, or SVO.

Kashaya (a Pomoan language spoken in Northern California) has set its parameters to specifier-initial and head-final. So it’s basic word order is “Subject-Object-Verb,” or SOV.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (32)

Malagasy (an Austronesian language spoken on Madagascar) has set its parameters to specifier-final and head-initial. It’s basic word order is “Verb-Object-Subject,” or VOS.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (33)

Lastly, Hixkaryana (a Carib language spoken in Brazil) has set its parameters to specifier-final and head-final. So it’s basic word order is “Object-Verb-Subject,” or OVS.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (34)

If you’re counting, you’ll notice that I’ve said nothing about whether the two other logically possible words orders of Subject, Verb, and Object exists: VSO and OSV. These cannot be straightforwardly derived by simply stipulating specifier and head directions. Something more (i.e., movement) must be added to the theory.

Nonetheless, K’iche’ (a Mayan language spoken in Guatemala) has a basic word order of “Verb-Subject-Object,” or VSO.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (35)

OSV is incredibly rare. This points to a very interesting distributional fact: while all possible orders exist, they don’t all exist with the same frequency. SOV is the predominant word-order cross-linguistically, accounting for about 40% the world’s languages. Next is SVO, accounting for about another 35%. The other categories account for the remaining 25%.

Interestingly, languages tend to be largely consistent in their head and specifier settings. That is, English is generally head-initial and specifier-initial. Kashaya is generally head-final and specifier-initial. Same with Malagasy and Hixkaryana.

It was proposed that the theory of syntax, coupled with a universal set of parameters can account for the entirety of the world’s languages. That is, suppose that there is a finite number of “switches,” and each language has a unique cumulative setting for each switch.This was (and still is) a popular idea. Even if it’s not entirely correct, it’s still a very handy way to think about language variation.

Parametric Variation (length: 2m 39s) Credit: Sydney Pritchard

This ends the first part of this book. We’ve built a theory of syntax: X-bar theory. We did so by looking at data, and thinking about how that data tells us. In the end, we decided that the X-bar schema was an efficient way to capture observed patterns in syntactic structures. It is worth reflecting again on what the benefit of the X-bar schema is. It is no longer necessary for us (as researchers) to try to figure out the “VP” rule, or the “NP” rule, because in fact, they’re the same rule! It’s just the X-bar tree.

Even more, consider the task of language acquisition. Every baby is confronted with a huge challenge: acquiring the intricacies of language. That challenge is greatly simplified if the baby intrinsically knows that everything they’re hearing conforms to X-bar syntax. The baby doesn’t have to learn about all the different things that can go in VP, nor all the different things that can go in NP. For the most part, the baby doesn’t have to figure out the constituency of the words they are hearing, because the constituency is essentially dictated by the X-bar schema (in most cases). This greatly simplifies what a baby needs to learn to acquire a language — any language. All they need to figure out (besides the words) are theparameters. Is the language head-initial or head-final? Is the language specifier-initial or specifier-final?

From here on out, we’re going to stick with the X-bar schema; we won’t make any more changes to the structure that we use. Going forward, we’re going to start talking aboutmanipulating structure. What happens when things start to move around?

Key Takeaways

  • Intermediate levels are found across all phrases.
  • The X-bar schema is empirically motivated by looking at constituency
  • The X-bar schema defines four positions: head, complement, specifier, adjunct.
  • Complements and adjuncts can be empirically distinguished through three tests.

The X-bar schema only permits maximallybinary branching trees. That is, according to the X-bar schema, a node can have at most two daughters. It can have fewer than two daughters, i.e., one or no daughters. But it cannot have three daughters.

In light of this constraint, we should revisit two of our phrase structure rules which seem to require a node to have three daughters. Recall our rules for coordination:

  • XP –> XP conj XP
  • X’ –> X’ conj X’
  • X –> X conj X

It’s not immediately clear how to map these rules into X’-syntax. Is there any way to demonstrate constituency that is consistent with binary branching structures? It turns out that there are a few tests that suggest an “asymmetric” constituent structure. Consider the following minimal, which involve (apparent) rightward movement of part of a coordinated element.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (36)

This data show that the conjunctionand groups together with thesecond conjunct, not the first.

Additional data comes from what is called Left-Branch Extraction. The basic observation is that sometimes you can move (something inside of) the leftmost part of a coordinate, but nothing in the rightmost part. An illustrative example comes from Japanese.[3] (The underlines indicate where the first word has moved from.)

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (37)

While an analysis of Left Branch Extraction is beyond the scope of this class, what we probably should conclude is that in coordination, the head of the coordination, i.e., and forms a constituent with the second element, to the exclusion of the first. It’s possible therefore to translate our phrase structure rules for coordination above into the following X’ compliant trees.

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (38)

This tree treats the first coordinate as a specifier, and the second as a complement. And crucially, it groups the head of ConjP together with the second coordinate. Thus, there is motivation for making even coordinated phrases abide by X’-structure.

  1. Note that the term "adverb" is a bit misleading: this aren't "adding" to the "verb".
  2. FYI Complement is spelled with an 'e'. It is not compliment.
  3. Bošković, Željko. "On the coordinate structure constraint, across-the-board-movement, phases, and labeling."Recent developments in phase theory(2020): 133-182.

definition

X-bar syntax – The Science of Syntax (2024)
Top Articles
38 chicken curry recipes
French Dip Sandwich Recipe - Lauren's Latest
Express Pay Cspire
Printable Whoville Houses Clipart
Kreme Delite Menu
What to Do For Dog Upset Stomach
Don Wallence Auto Sales Vehicles
Gabriel Kuhn Y Daniel Perry Video
Devotion Showtimes Near Mjr Universal Grand Cinema 16
Doublelist Paducah Ky
What happens if I deposit a bounced check?
Craigslist Nj North Cars By Owner
Natureza e Qualidade de Produtos - Gestão da Qualidade
Alaska Bücher in der richtigen Reihenfolge
Brenna Percy Reddit
Mycarolinas Login
C-Date im Test 2023 – Kosten, Erfahrungen & Funktionsweise
Craigslist Pets Southern Md
Programmieren (kinder)leicht gemacht – mit Scratch! - fobizz
General Info for Parents
Grasons Estate Sales Tucson
Youravon Comcom
Dutch Bros San Angelo Tx
Clear Fork Progress Book
Mc Donald's Bruck - Fast-Food-Restaurant
Espn Horse Racing Results
Rufus Benton "Bent" Moulds Jr. Obituary 2024 - Webb & Stephens Funeral Homes
Georgia Cash 3 Midday-Lottery Results & Winning Numbers
Theater X Orange Heights Florida
Gs Dental Associates
The 15 Best Sites to Watch Movies for Free (Legally!)
Keyn Car Shows
Viduthalai Movie Download
CohhCarnage - Twitch Streamer Profile & Bio - TopTwitchStreamers
What Is The Lineup For Nascar Race Today
Ucm Black Board
Pensacola 311 Citizen Support | City of Pensacola, Florida Official Website
Bimar Produkte Test & Vergleich 09/2024 » GUT bis SEHR GUT
Go Upstate Mugshots Gaffney Sc
Edict Of Force Poe
Go Smiles Herndon Reviews
Boone County Sheriff 700 Report
Indio Mall Eye Doctor
2700 Yen To Usd
Live Delta Flight Status - FlightAware
705 Us 74 Bus Rockingham Nc
Cch Staffnet
Star Sessions Snapcamz
Latina Webcam Lesbian
Wrentham Outlets Hours Sunday
Supervisor-Managing Your Teams Risk – 3455 questions with correct answers
Latest Posts
Article information

Author: Wyatt Volkman LLD

Last Updated:

Views: 6161

Rating: 4.6 / 5 (66 voted)

Reviews: 81% of readers found this page helpful

Author information

Name: Wyatt Volkman LLD

Birthday: 1992-02-16

Address: Suite 851 78549 Lubowitz Well, Wardside, TX 98080-8615

Phone: +67618977178100

Job: Manufacturing Director

Hobby: Running, Mountaineering, Inline skating, Writing, Baton twirling, Computer programming, Stone skipping

Introduction: My name is Wyatt Volkman LLD, I am a handsome, rich, comfortable, lively, zealous, graceful, gifted person who loves writing and wants to share my knowledge and understanding with you.